The Competition between Legal Orders - Max-Planck

Transcrição

The Competition between Legal Orders - Max-Planck
International Law Research; Vol. 3, No. 1; 2014
ISSN 1927-5234
E-ISSN 1927-5242
Published by Canadian Center of Science and Education
The Competition between Legal Orders
Anne Peters1,2
1
Max Planck Institute for Comparative Public Law and International Law, Heidelberg, Germany
2
International Law and Constitutional Law at the University of Basel, Switzerland
Correspondence: Anne Peters, Im Neuenheimer Feld 535, D-69120 Heidelberg, Germany. E-mail:
[email protected]
Received: August 25, 2013
doi:10.5539/ilr.v3n1p45
Accepted: October 8, 2013
Online Published: April 15, 2014
URL: http://dx.doi.org/10.5539/ilr.v3n1p45
Abstract
This paper asks two questions. The first is an analytical one: does the reconstruction of the sovereign activity of
law-making and legal reform as a competitive bid have an analytical benefit on which doctrinal insights in
particular can build? The second question is a normative one: should the competitive paradigm serve as a
normative guideline for the legislator?
The first question is answered with a “yes, but …”. The reconstruction of legal reform as “competition” on a
market opens up a new perspective. A variety of different law-selection mechanisms are at work in the tripolar
relationship between persons subject to law (“customers”) and competing legal systems (or orders). But the
competitive cycle is often interrupted by weak selection pressure and selection inaccuracy.
The answer to the second, normative question is developed with a view to five legal principles: liberty, equality,
democracy, the social principle, and the public interest. The competition between legal systems partly
undermines those principles. This finding suggests that this competition must be adequately framed by a legal
meta order. That meta order should, inter alia, ban unfair regulatory practices, establish rules of international
cooperation, harmonise some procedures, and it should guarantee respect for some inalienable principles.
Keywords: law market, choice of law, voice and exit, race to the bottom, public interest, harmful tax
competition, normative dumping
1. Introduction
In the age of globalisation, competition between Nation States is perceived sharply. The Davos World Economic
Forum, the annual meeting between top executives of global companies and politicians, regularly publishes
“Global Competitiveness Reports”. These reports identify various factors of the national legal systems which
inhibit or promote business activity: labour legislation, tax rates and tax regulations, foreign-exchange
regulations, property rights, judicial independence, reliability of police services and protection of minority
shareholders’ interests, and on this basis the reports establish a ranking of the countries.1
Such rankings prompt countries to actively advertise their own legal system. Under the heading “Law Made in
Germany”, a brochure published by Germany’s Federal Chamber of Civil Law Notaries in conjunction with
other associations of the legal profession and with a foreword by the Federal Minister of Justice, promoted
German law with the catchwords “global – effective – cost-efficient.”2 The publication extols the benefits of
codification, praises the lack of cross-examination and punitive damages and stresses the legal certainty created
with the German Land Register and Commercial Register. The German advertising brochure reacted to the
English publication “England and Wales: The Jurisdiction of Choice”, published by the Law Society of England
1
According to the report for 2012/2013, Switzerland ranks first, the Netherlands occupy rank 5, followed by Germany (6) and the U.S. (7)
(WEF. Global Competitiveness Report, 2009-2010 (http://www.weforum.org/reports/global-competitiveness-report-2012-2013). The World
Bank, too, publishes so-called “Doing Business” reports on a regular basis which allow for the comparison of legal provisions of nearly all
States in the world, the latest report is benchmarked as of June 2012. http://www.doingbusiness.org/rankings.
2
The Federal Chamber of German Civil Law Notaries (Bundesnotarkammer), the German Federal Bar (Bundesrechtsanwaltskammer), the
German Bar Association (Deutscher Anwaltverein), the German Notaries’ Association (Deutscher Notarverein) and the German Judges
Association (Deutscher Richterbund). (Eds.). Law Made in Germany. http://www.lawmadeingermany.de.
45
www.ccsenet.org/ilr
International Law Research
Vol. 3, No. 1; 2014
and Wales, with a foreword by the British Secretary of State for Justice.3 These PR campaigns are reminiscent
of the traditional so-called “systems competition” between common law and civil law.
2. State versus Market
PR activities of that type have sparked a controversy in legal scholarship.4 The fundamental criticism is that the
mode of interaction called competition (see for the meaning of “competition” below section 3) is irreconcilable
with the organisational form of the State. Some legal scholars claim that it would be a categorical mistake to
apply the concept of competition to States, because – so the argument runs – the organising principle of
“sovereignty” is diametrically opposed to the organising principle of “competition”. From that perspective, law
is simply no product suitable to be placed in competition.5
In economics, Werner Sinn writes, with the same thrust, that “nothing could be more misleading than the usual
conclusion by analogy” between State and market.6 The fundamental economic objection is that competition
between legal orders constitutes a duplication of market failure. If market failure is regarded as a potential
justification for State intervention, the State must act as a stopgap. But if the State is itself “marketed”, this is no
longer possible. The critique is that re-introducing the market by the back door of competition between legal
orders would make the failures that caused the State to intervene in the first place resurface at the higher level of
intergovernmental competition.7
However, there seems to be no consensus among economists about the usefulness of the theory of market failure
to justify the performance of certain functions by the State. Contrary to the beliefs held in the traditional field of
public finance, proponents of public choice rather opine that State intervention in the market process is normally
pernicious. On the whole, the question of the applicability of the market mode to the State and its legal order
appears to be still unresolved in economic theory.
From the point of view of constitutional law (that is the body of fundamental legal norms governing a polity
which are often but not inevitably codified in a specific legal document), we might say simplistically that
“market” and “State” represent the two basic and partly antagonist organising principles of any human society,
namely freedom and equality. The market and its mode of competition stand for freedom and individuality,
whereas the State and its law, in contrast, stand for the general public interest and thus rather for equality.
Further dichotomies spring to one’s mind: coercion by the State versus voluntariness in the market;
unilateral-hierarchical modes of government versus contractually-horizontal action in the market; public interest
pursued by the State versus self-interest pursued by market participants; the principle of limited government
versus profit maximisation in the market. Above all, the State is obliged to respect the rule of law, while the
providers in the market are basically free to act at whim. These dichotomies suggest that the functional logic of a
State is fundamentally different from that of the market. That logic might be opposed to an application of the
concept of competition to the State. Nevertheless, the rankings and PR measures mentioned in the introduction
show that States (or rather the governing elites) do at least believe they are in competition.
3. Problématique and Basic Concepts
The divergence between the practice of competition among States and the theory of irreconcilable paradigms
(States as opposed to markets) provokes two questions. The first is an analytical one: does the
reconceptualisation of the sovereign activity of law-making and of law reform as a competitive bid yield
anything for a legal analysis? The second question is a normative one: should the competitive paradigm serve as
a normative guideline for legislators?
On the analytical plane, we must first briefly recapitulate the meaning of competition. Here a distinction should
be drawn between competition in a broad and in a narrow sense. An ordinary dictionary defines competition (in a
broad sense) as “the act or process of trying to get or win something (such as a prize or a higher level of success)
that someone else is also trying to get or win”.8 Put differently, when two or more players compete to obtain a
3
Law Society of England and Wales. (Ed.). England and Wales: The Jurisdiction of Choice. www. lawsociety.org.uk.
4
Seminally Kieninger, E.-M. (2002). Wettbewerb der Privatrechtsordnungen im Europäischen Binnenmarkt. Tübingen, Germany: Mohr
Siebeck.
5
Kirchhof P. (2005). Freiheitlicher Wettbewerb und staatliche Autonomie – Solidarität. ORDO, 56, 39-45 (40); Grzeszick B. (2003).
Hoheitskonzept – Wettbewerbskonzept. In J. Isensee, & P. Kirchhof (Eds.), Handbuch des Staatsrechts (Vol. IV, 3rd ed., pp. 367 et seq.).
Heidelberg, Germany: C.F. Müller.
6
Sinn, H. W. (2003). The New Systems Competition (p. 7), Oxford, England: Wiley.
7
Sinn, H. W. Competition (note 6), p. 6.
8
Competition. In Merriam-Webster Online. Retrieved November 14, 2013, from http://m-w.com/dictionary/competition.
46
www.ccsenet.org/ilr
International Law Research
Vol. 3, No. 1; 2014
good, there is competition in a broad sense. The prime example is sport, in which a number of athletes compete
for a title. The rivalry between political units for political and economic supremacy has – starting with Athens
and Sparta – always been described as such competition in the broad sense, also comprising competition between
the respective legal order (e.g. democracy versus monarchy).9
Contemporary economic analysis does not relate to such “bipolar” relationships, but takes the market as its basis.
Competition is viewed as an interaction structure of the market. The market, in turn, is the point where supply
and demand meet. Here the relationship is “tripolar”, because customers come into play, to whose demand a
provider reacts. In the terminology of economics, competition within a market consists in a parallel process
(between the competing suppliers) and an exchange process (between the suppliers and the demanders).10 This
is a fundamentally different interaction structure from the “bipolar” one. This sort of competition (on a market)
is, according to general usage of the word, “the effort of two or more parties acting independently to secure the
business of a third party by offering the most favorable terms.”11
From the competition perspective, the merchandise (or product) supplied is − in the context that this paper
examines − the entire legal order. Similar terms used for this phenomenon, the competition of legal orders, or for
closely related phenomena are: “competition of institutions, 12 “systems competition”, 13 “jurisdictional
competition”,14 and “regulatory competition.” In this paper, I will use those terms interchangeably.
Moving to the second level, the normative analysis, we must ask what the yardsticks for the evaluation of the
(“tripolar”) market competition about the product (the law viz. an entire legal order) are. From a purely
economic perspective, the yardstick against which to evaluate (potential) benefits of regulatory competition is
solely its capacity to realise the generally acknowledged benefits of competition. These are: better products, a
greater choice, and lower prices. But when is the product (the legal order) better? It is better – within the
competition paradigm − not when it fulfils predetermined independent criteria, but when it satisfies the
customers’ individual preferences, which in turn relate to goods which are shaped by the law, such as transport
infrastructure, schools, work, environmental quality, or the tax burden. From that perspective, competition of
legal orders is a good thing to the extent that it causes States to develop new law and thus improves the product
law, and when it leaves persons subject to the laws a choice (of law).
From a legal perspective, however, the merits (or drawbacks) of regulatory competition must be (also) assessed
against the yardstick of constitutional principles. Put differently, the lawyerly examination needs to assess and
evaluate the benefits of that competition process with a view at legal criteria which do not necessarily coincide
with personal preferences of individuals, such as capacity of the competition process to secure respect of legal
(and even constitutional) principles, namely security, freedom, and equality. It is difficult to assess or even
measure the capacity of laws (or an entire legal system) to promote and respect those legal principles. In the
recent years, indicators have been developed to this end.15 Qualitative and quantitative indicators (structural
indicators, procedural indicators, and outcome indicators) are being used both to guide the formulation of
policies and laws, and to measure the quality and the implementation of law with the methods of sociological
research. Such indicators may be used to assess the state of implementation and realisation of human rights
guarantees including social rights (health, education, and so on) and political rights (right to life, freedom from
torture, and so on). But it is important to keep in mind that indicators, while complementing assessments with a
strong qualitative dimension (e.g. findings of human rights violations), may not replace those.16
9
Cf Aristotle. (2000). Politics, Book III (1279b), Oxford, England: Clarendon Press.
10
See for these terms Hopmann, E. (1967). Wettbewerb als Norm der Wettbewerbspolitik. ORDO, 18, 77 et seq. (88 et seq.).
11
“Competition”. In Merriam-Webster Online. Retrieved November 14, 2013, from http://m-w.com/dictionary/competition.
12
See e.g. Bergh, A., & Höijer, R. (Eds.) (2008). Institutional Competition, Cheltenham, England: Edward Elgar Publishing.
13
See e.g. Becker U., & Schön, W. (Eds.) (2005). Steuer- und Sozialstaat im europäischen Systemwettbewerb, Tübingen, Germany: Mohr
Siebeck; Breton, A., (1996). Competitive Governments, Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press.
14
See Bratton, W. W., & McCahery, J. A. (1997). The New Economics of Jurisdictional Competition: Devolutionary Federalism in a
Second-Best World. Georgetown Law Journal, 86, 201-278.
15
Candler, J., Holder, H., Hosali, S., Payne, A. M., Tsang, T., Vizard, P. (2011). Human Rights Measurement Framework: Prototype Panels,
Indicator Set and Evidence Base. Equality and Human Rights Commission (Scotland); United Nations, Office of the Human Rights
Commissioner (UNHCR) (2012). Human Rights Indicators: A Guide to Measurement and Implementation. See in scholarship: Landmann, T.
& Carvalho, E. (2010). Measuring Human Rights. London, England: Routledge; Langford, M., & Fikuda-Parr, S. (2011). The Turn to
Metrics. Nordic Journal of Human Rights, 30, 222-236; Davis, K. E., Fisher, A., Kingsbury, B. Merry, S. E. (Eds.) (2012). Governance by
Indicators: Global Power through Quantification and Rankings. Oxford, England: Oxford University Press.
16
UNHCR (note 15), p. 21.
47
www.ccsenet.org/ilr
International Law Research
Vol. 3, No. 1; 2014
The paper will proceed, first, with the positive analysis (section 4), and then move to the normative analysis of
the competition between legal orders (section 5).
4. Positive Analysis of the Competition Paradigm
What is the analytical added value of applying the competition paradigm to legal orders? The answer depends
first of all on the rigour of the analogy, which will be examined in what follows.
4.1 The Product and its Providers
The legal order as the product: the object of the supposed competition would be the legal order (or legal system;
used synonymously in this paper). Law is conceived as the product or merchandise. Just like a raw material, law
seems to be a pre-product for the actual production of goods.17 This raw material is offered on the law-market.18
(The marketability of the law cannot a priori be ruled out on the basis that the framework of the market for its
part must be constituted by (an additional set of) legal norms.) One characteristic of an entire “legal order” as
one product is its high degree of bundling. This package can barely be unbundled by its users. Another feature is
that although the billions of citizens-customers have billions of different preferences, they only have an
extremely small choice among only 192 national legal orders.
Globalisation brings to an end the State monopoly of law: competition presupposes a plurality of providers or
suppliers. In contrast, constitutional theory has traditionally assumed that the State is a monopolist. The State has
been regarded as the sole ultimate source of all law. From a traditional constitutional law-perspective, foreign
law or privately-generated law cannot apply within the national territory of a State unless the State authorises
such an application, either explicitly or implicitly.
However, globalisation and global governance have called into question the traditional monopoly position of the
State as the provider of law. Natural and moral persons subject to State-made law have at least some limited
physical exit options. Also, choice-of-law-options seem to be extending. Finally, intergovernmental and
non-governmental actors play an increasingly independent role in law-making. Overall, globalisation has created
a new situation which has been called a “new systems competition”.19
State and non-State providers: in this “new” competition, the Nation States, more specifically the legislative
bodies and the courts, are the providers of the “legal order” as a merchandise. Further providers are the
constituent units of federal States, regional and local authorities such as municipalities, and international or
supranational organisations. National legal systems are in competition not only with one another, but also with
“supra”- and “infra”-national systems. A vertical or multi-level competition notably takes place between EU-law
and the domestic law of the Member State, but of course only in fields where the law-making competence does
not remain exclusively with the Member States or has not been exclusively conferred on the EU. Multi-level
competition within the EU thus only takes place in areas of shared competences in terms of Art. 2 sec. 2, 5 and
Art. 4-6 TFEU.
To a limited extent, social players are providers of (sub-)legal systems, too. Throughout history, those systems
were often in competition with State-made law. One example is the medieval rivalry between ecclesiastical and
secular law, which was presumably a decisive driving force for the development of modern legal orders in
Europe.20 Today, non-State actors produce a diverse range of standards, extending from indigenous law21
through the lex mercatoria to corporate codes of conduct. Legal pluralism perceives these social groups as
original producers of law.22 The competition paradigm underscores the legal pluralist view: if law is a product, it
17
Heine, K. (2003). Regulierungswettbewerb im Gesellschaftsrecht (p. 100), Berlin, Germany: Duncker & Humblot. On law as a product see
also Eidenmüller, H. (2009). Recht als Produkt. JuristenZeitung (JZ) 64, 641-652.
18
O’Hara, E., & Ribstein, L. E. (2009). The Law Market, Oxford, England: Oxford University Press.
19
Sinn. Competition (note 6).
20
Berman, H. (1998). The Western Legal Tradition: The Interaction of Revolutionary Innovation and Evolutionary Growth. In P. Bernholz,
M. E. Streit, R. Vaubel (Eds.), Political Competition, Innovation, and Growth: A Historical Analysis (pp. 35 et seq. (pp. 38-9)). Berlin,
Germany: Springer Verlag on “late eleventh century with the church’s establishment of an external forum, a hierarchy of ecclesiastical courts
with exclusive jurisdiction in some matters … The pluralism of Western law was a source of legal sophistication and of legal growth. It was
also a source of freedom.”
21
See on the right to promote, develop and maintain indigenous “juridical systems” Art. 34 of the United Nations Declaration on the Rights
of Indigenous Peoples of 13 September 2007 (UN-Doc. A/61/L. 67).
22
Teubner, G. (1997). “Global Bukowina”: Legal Pluralism in the World Society. In G. Teubner (Ed.), Global Law Without a State (pp. 3-28).
Farnham, England: Ashgate; De Sousa Santos, B. (2002). Toward a New Legal Common Sense (2nd ed.). Cambridge, England: Cambridge
University Press.
48
www.ccsenet.org/ilr
International Law Research
Vol. 3, No. 1; 2014
can, like any other merchandise, be manufactured and offered by private individuals, and there would be no
reason to have a State monopoly on the production of law.23 It would be consistent with the competition
paradigm if the State created incentives for private actors to produce the “merchandise” law by granting them
copyright protection or by providing other legal schemes which might facilitate non-State standard setting.
4.2 Law-Customers and Their Choice of Law
In the legal orders market, those who are subject to the law are the “law-customers”, the “law clients”, or those
who “demand” law, in their capacity as voters, taxpayers, owners of financial or real capital, and consumers.
What is known as “regulatory arbitrage” by those customers, that is, the choice of the legal order they prefer, can
take place in various modalities. The basic ones are “voice” and “exit”,24 although further modalities exist as
well.
4.2.1 Direct Choice of Law: Some Examples
In democracies, the “voice” is normally cast in political elections, while it can also be raised in citizens’ protests
and lobbying activity. Besides the democratic process, numerous other (much more direct) mechanisms allow
the “law clients” to express their preferences for a specific law or legal order.
The usual mode of choosing law happens under conflict-of-law-provisions (private international law) which
probably all national legal systems possess in form of codes or case-law. This type of choice of law is available
in various transnational constellations (transnational contracts; transnational families; torts, etc.), and normally
does not require the involved parties to change their physical location. The rules of private international law may
not only leave a choice to the persons subject to the law but sometimes also to the law-applying authorities. For
example, a judge may be asked, in a family case, to decide which law should govern the relationships of a child
to its parents (custody etc.) if those have different nationalities and/or different domiciles. Some systems of
private international law will allow the judge to compare the relevant rules of the various involved States and
choose to apply those which are in the best interest of the child. However, in this constellation, it is not the actual
“consumer” (the child itself) which chooses, and the judge’s choice does not exert pressure on the law-maker to
modify its legal order.
The choice can also be realised in the field of legal procedure, for example through arbitration clauses. The
choice of a specific tribunal or of any other dispute settlement body often determines which law will be applied
to the merits of a dispute. Here the market analogy is present in the concept of “forum-shopping”.25
Another mode of choosing law is the purchase of products that satisfy the standards of a foreign legal system. If
a purchaser buys French cheese made from unpasteurised milk, he/she decides in favour of French production
standards and accepts the danger to his/her own health. In any case, the consumer opts for this part of the legal
order – the hygiene regulations – with his/her purse.26
4.2.2 Indirect Choice of Law through “Exit”
In principle, people can also choose a legal order through “exit.” They may emigrate if they are dissatisfied with
the legal order they live under.27 Already the medieval principle that “city air… makes one free after a year and
a day” which referred to the choice of law through physical displacement, by emigration from the countryside
into a European medieval city. Another example is the “beneficium emigrandi” enshrined in the Peace of
Augsburg of 1555, which gave individuals a right to emigrate to a different territory in which their religious
creed was accepted by the ruler. Today, political refugees are law-consumers looking for a free and fair legal
system. Migration for economic reasons can also be interpreted as indirect “voting with the feet” against the
emigrants’ poor home country’s legal orders, because the underdevelopment which migrants seek to escape has
its roots, inter alia, in the legal system itself, for example in deficient protection of property rights or insufficient
laws against corruption. The same mechanism, namely “voting with the feet” against deteriorating living
23
Bachmann, G. (2006). Private Ordnung: Grundlagen ziviler Regelsetzung (pp. 50 and 52). Tübingen, Germany: Mohr Siebeck.
24
Hirschman, A. O. (1970). Exit, Voice and Loyalty: Responses to Decline in Firms, Organizations and States. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press.
25
Cf. Thompson Denning, A. known as Lord Denning (1972). The Atlantic Star. All English Law Reports 3, 705 et seq. (709): “This right to
come here is not confined to Englishmen. It extends to any friendly foreigner. … You may call this ‘forum shopping’ if you please, but if the
forum is England, it is a good place to shop, both for the quality of the goods and the speed of service.”
26
Muir-Watt, H. (2004). Aspects économiques du droit international privé. Recueil des cours de l’Académie de la Haye, 307, 25-383 (54).
The buyer exercises – as is said in the jargon – his/her consumer sovereignty and casts his/her “consumer-vote”.
27
See below on the human rights-quality of the right to emigrate note 87.
49
www.ccsenet.org/ilr
International Law Research
Vol. 3, No. 1; 2014
conditions which partly result from municipal laws (in the area of education, taxes, infrastructure) may be one
explanatory factor for the phenomenon of shrinking cities, notably in the developed world.28
However, the “exit”-mode of choosing law or an entire legal system is not equally available to all consumers of
the law. Only financial capital enjoys full mobility in fact, because its mobility costs are extremely low. In
contrast, due to high mobility costs (such as human and cultural losses), natural persons remain rather immobile,
except at the top and bottom ends of the income scale. Natural persons tend to be more mobile only across
jurisdictions which extend over a very small surface area. It is no coincidence that Charles Tiebout established
his famous competition model for U.S. municipalities (not with a view to the entire Nation State),29 and that
legal competition among the Swiss Cantons (which are very small) is fierce.30
Besides individual emigration, the so-to-speak collective emigration of citizens along with their territory through
secession, can in the competition paradigm be reconstructed as a choice of law, made by that collective.31 Some
economists do in fact interpret a group’s threat with secession as a permissible modality of choice that may put
legislators under a pressure to adapt the law of the territory.32 A scholarly proposal to create functional,
overlapping jurisdictions, a form of administration unions, relies on the same logic, namely to allow for
consumer-adapted legal sub-systems for defined issue areas, detached to a certain extent from territory.33
However, under current public international law, secession is basically prohibited. This means that the secession
of a territory from an existing State – which would be consistent in the competition paradigm – is for legal
reasons unavailable as a modality of choice of law.
A different mode of choosing law is to change one’s nationality. This might be conceptualised as a kind of “exit”,
too, because it leads to the applicability of an entire new legal order by virtue of the naturalising State’s
jurisdiction over its citizens. For companies within the meaning of Article 54 sec. 2 TFEU, it is easy to adopt a
new organisational law or new articles of association through a company’s re-incorporation under a new legal
order. When this is done in a constellation in which the applicable choice-of-law-rules follow the incorporation
theory (as opposed to the seat theory), a complete exchange of the constitutive law of the company is possible
without even having to relocate physically the main administrative seat of the company.34
The situation is different for natural persons. With the idea of competition in mind, economists have proposed
tradable citizenships that would be able to be resold when switching to a different jurisdiction.35 This proposal
appears difficult to reconcile with the ideational and permanent nature of nationality. Yet, it is precisely this type
of choice of legal order that is currently popular in Eastern Europe. In particular, the Russian Federation has
generously bestowed Russian citizenship on residents of neighbouring States, without the latter having to take up
residence in Russia. Within the two separatist territories of Georgia, in South Ossetia and Abkhazia, the
inhabitants scramble to obtain the Russian citizenship which entitles them, inter alia, to Russian social-welfare
benefits and which enables them to participate in the EU Visa facilitation programme.36
A yet different type of “exit” is the withdrawal of a Member State from an international organisation. From the
competition perspective, such a withdrawal amounts to a choice of law, too, namely opting against the
28
See UN Habitat (Ed.) State of the World’s Cities 2008/2009 (pp. 40-47). New York, NY: UN; Richardson, H. W. & Nam C. W. (Eds.).
(2013). Shrinking Cities: A Global Perspective. London, England: Routledge; Pallagst, K. M., Wiechmann T., Martinez-Fernandez, C. (Eds.).
(2013). Shrinking Cities: International Perspectives and Policy Implications. London, England: Routledge.
29
Tiebout, C. M. (1956). A Pure Theory of Local Expenditures. The Journal of Political Economy, 64, 416-424.
30
See the empirical research by Feld, L. (2006). Regulatory Competition and Federalism in Switzerland: Diffusion by Horizontal and
Vertical Interaction. In CREMA (Center for Research in Economics, Management and the Arts) Working Paper No. 2006-22.
http://www.crema-research.ch/papers/2006-22.pdf.
31
See on ideas of entrepreneurs in Silicon Valley to secede from the USA in order to escape regulation Giridharadas, A. (2013, October 28).
Silicon Valley Roused by Secession Calls. New York Times.
32
See Buchanan J., & Faith, R. (1987). Secession and the Limits of Taxation: Toward a Theory of Internal Exit. American Economic Review,
77, 1023-31.
33
See in support of this Frey, B., & Eichenberger, R. (1999). The New Democratic Federalism for Europe: Functional Overlapping and
Competing Jurisdictions. Cheltenham, England: Edward Elgar Publishing.
34
ECJ, case C-212/97, Centros Ltd v. Erhvervs-og Selkabsstyrelsen, ECR 1999, I-1459; case C-208/00, Überseering, ECR 2002, I-9919;
case C-167/01, Inspire Art, ECR 2003, I-10155; case C-210/06, Cartesio Oktató és Szolgáltató bt, ECR 2008 I-3468. Cf. Advocate General A.
La Pergola in Centros, para. 20 at note 49 referring to C. D. Ehlermann on “competition among rules”.
35
Tullock, G. (1997). Trading Citizenship. Kyklos 50, 251-252.
36
See Independent International Fact-Finding Commission. (2009). Report of September 2009, “Passportisation” (Vol. II, Chapter 3, Part 3),
147 et seq. www.ceiig.ch.
50
www.ccsenet.org/ilr
International Law Research
Vol. 3, No. 1; 2014
organisation’s legal regime. Such a withdrawal from international organisations is legal (see for the EU Art. 50
TEU), and hence constitutes a real choice-of-law-modality.
4.3 The Lack of a Competition Cycle
The direct or indirect choice of a legal system that can be exercised by the law consumers in the modalities
described above leads to actual competition only if these choices exert pressure on the law-providers to adapt, so
that the latter will indeed reform the legal order so as to satisfy the preferences expressed by the consumers. The
competition paradigm fits only if it can be reasonably said that law consumers pay a “price” for the legal order
they desire, and that the law-provider makes profit when it responds to legal consumers’ wishes. Only then, a
real competition cycle exists.
In this section, I shall discuss the incentives created for the providers of law through the “consumers’” election
of a political party that will then dominate parliament, and through the consumers’ threat with emigration (i.e.
choice through “voice” and “exit”). I will not dwell on the incentives created for law-providers through the other
modalities of choice mentioned above, i.e. through the purchase of foreign goods, the threat with secession, or
the acquisition of a foreign nationality. The pressure to adapt the law exercised by these expressions of
preference is rather weak, anyway.
Any competition cycle is completely lacking in the ordinary process of reception of foreign legal institutions and
systems, for example the reception of Western constitutional institutions in Central and Eastern democracies in
the 1990s. Although such reception processes are often described as “yardstick competition”,37 competition in
the sense described above does not exist. The reason is that the reception processes are not decisively set in
motion by the demand of the citizen-“customers”. Law-makers adopt foreign law and institutions primarily for
reasons which are not connected with the “customers”. And on the side of the “law-exporter”, the export of the
domestic institutions does not lead to its own legal system being reformed in response to “customer” requests.
Thus, the cycle that is typical of “tripolar” market competition, a cycle in the sense that the providers react to the
customers’ preferences, is not present in the context of legal reception. Labelling legal reception as yardstick
competition is therefore misleading.
More fundamental problems attach to the competition paradigm, when applied to the legal order: there is no
contract and no price. First, no enforceable contract may be concluded on the product law. The contrat social is
not justiciable. Second, even proponents of the idea of competition between legal orders do not take the view
that this means that citizens should pay money in exchange for legal services, for example, for obtaining a
building permit. Rather, the “payment” of a “price” for the law is considered to be present in three different
items: in the voter’s vote, in his continued residence in the State, or in his payment of taxes. All three behaviours
can only with difficulties be reconstructed as “paying a price” for a good.
This is most obvious with taxes. From a legal perspective, taxes are by definition not the remuneration for
specific services provided in return by the State. The level of tax that is paid in a given State is not determined by
the State-services provided to individuals, last but not least because these are virtually impossible to measure.
The tax rate is therefore calculated on the basis and justified with a view to the taxpayers’ capacity to pay. The
State’s revenue from taxes and fees (for example, the company registration fee in the U.S. State of Delaware38),
is then – from an orthodox tax law perspective – not used to satisfy specific wishes of taxpayers, notably not
preferences concerning the shape of the legal order, but simply as a general governance resource of the State.
In the end, the so-called “competition” of laws of legal systems is just one element in a purely economic
competition among States. “Competing” law-makers strive to generate economic wealth in their State, either
because they idealistically seek to serve the public interest, and/or because they seek to preserve their position of
political power. A flourishing economy is normally “rewarded” by voters. However, the cycle postulated in the
competition paradigm – from the customer’s wish to product innovation and back to the customer – that is, the
competition cycle, hardly runs really smoothly in relation to legal orders. 39 On the provider’s side, the
law-makers would need to have precise data on the mobility and the other choice-of-law-decisions made by their
customers, interpret them and make appropriate offers to improve their legal product. But in reality, the
law-providers – the political parties – can hardly attribute the causes of losing voters to specific aspects of the
law in force. This means that political elections do not exercise pressure on the law-provider to furnish a
37
For the term “yardstick-competition” see Shleifer, A. (1985). A Theory of Yardstick Competition. The Rand Journal of Economics, 16, 319
et seq.
38
A considerable part of Delaware’s budget is financed by the revenues of this franchise tax (30 Del. C, Section 1902(b)(6)).
39
See on this Kieninger. Wettbewerb (note 4), pp. 51-65.
51
www.ccsenet.org/ilr
International Law Research
Vol. 3, No. 1; 2014
modified product, new laws. The same lack of pressure is absent with regard to “choices” through exit. Migrants
exert hardly any pressure on law-furnishers to adapt their product, either on the deficient legal system that they
are fleeing or on the destination State, which often would prefer to get rid of them again. Legal reforms are
therefore hardly ever triggered clearly by choice-of-law-decisions made by natural persons, be it through “voice”
or through “exit”. The only constellation in which a cycle might be said to exist is in the tax-law competition
between jurisdictions. Industries can plausibly threaten to relocate abroad and thereby exercise pressure on
tax-law-makers, which will then adapt their product (tax law) in order to keep or attract investors within their
jurisdiction.
4.4 Conclusion: Reconstructing Legal Evolution as a Competition about the Product “Law”
So does it have an analytical added-value to consider law as a product, the State as its producer, and the citizen
as the customer? As explained above, we do not need the market paradigm to understand better the mechanism
of legal reception. But with regard to other constellations, we have seen that a host of differing law
selection-mechanisms are at work in the “tripolar” relationship between the consumers of law and the multiple
competing legal orders. These mechanisms rarely concern entire legal orders, but rather specific legal
sub-systems. For example, the option of choosing law under conflict-of-law-provisions is not available in public
law (only in private law, such as contracts, torts, and family law). Next, tax-law competition40 is most of all a
form of territorial competition. In contrast, competition in contract law is a largely de-territorialised form of
competition. Competition in company law41 is both: territorial and de-territorialised. Finally, the decision to
purchase a foreign good concerns only product standards (and these only marginally), so that it appears artificial
to describe that behaviour as a choice of law.
Overall, the translation from the sphere of the “sovereign” to the sphere of “competition” is a useful heuristic.
Indeed, the act of translation sharpens the eye for differences, that is for the specific characteristics of the State
and for what distinguishes it from the market. The reconstruction of the legal reform as “competition” on a “law
market” opens up a new perspective, which can be fruitful, but only partially.
Most of all, no legal policy recommendation can be derived directly from this diagnosis. Such recommendations
depend on the normative assessment of the phenomena which follow in the next section.
5. Normative Assessment of Competition between Legal Orders
The description and interpretation of the evolution of legal orders as a kind of competition allows to identify
both negative and positive effects of the phenomena. In a normative perspective, I will confine myself to
assessing the effects of the legal systems competition on five legal principles (or “goods” − in the competition
paradigm): freedom, equality, democracy, the social principle and the public interest.
5.1 Ensuring Freedom through Competition between Legal Orders
The most fundamental justification for competition between legal orders is that this competition enhances
freedom. Already Max Weber maintained that the liberation and formation of a national bourgeoisie was a result
of competition between modern States for “freely moving” capital.42 Today, public-choice scholars in particular
emphasise that the threat of emigration (of natural and moral persons) compels States to remain “lean” with their
legal order, which, it is claimed, enhances the citizens’ freedom.
However, it does not follow from this potentially freedom-ensuring function of inter-State competition that the
conventional, non-fiscal instruments for controlling and restraining the power of the State have become obsolete.
The classic juridical mechanisms for limiting political power remain relevant, because competition between
States and their legal systems does not suffice to eliminate the potentials for abuses of governmental power.
40
See for legal literature on tax competition Avi-Yonah, R. S. (2000). Globalisation, Tax Competition and the Fiscal Crisis of the Welfare
State. Harvard Law Review, 113, 1573 et seq.; Schön, W. (2002-3). Steuerwettbewerb in Europa. Archiv des schweizerischen Abgabenrechts
71, 337-383; Schmehl, A. (2009). Nationales Steuerrecht im internationalen Steuerwettbewerb. In W. Schön, & K. E. M. Beck (Eds.),
Zukunftsfragen des deutschen Steuerrechts, MPI Studies on Intellectual Property, Competition and Tax Law, (pp. 99-123). Berlin, Heidelberg,
Germany: Springer Verlag. From economics Gerken, L., Märkt, J., Schick, G. (2000). Internationaler Steuerwettbewerb. Tübingen, Germany:
Mohr Siebeck; Höijer, R., Tax Competition and Tax Cartels. In Bergh & Höijer (note 12), 129-154.
41
See Romano, R. (1993). The Genius of American Corporate Law. Washington DC: Aei Press; Heine, K. (2003). Regulierungswettbewerb
im Gesellschaftsrecht. Berlin, Germany: Duncker & Humblot; Teichmann, C. (2006). Binnenmarktkonformes Gesellschaftsrecht. Berlin,
Germany: de Gruyter Recht.
42
Weber, M. (1923). Wirtschaftsgeschichte: Abriss der universalen Sozial- und Wirtschaftsgeschichte (pp. 288-289). München, Leipzig,
Germany: Duncker & Humblot.
52
www.ccsenet.org/ilr
International Law Research
Vol. 3, No. 1; 2014
Competition between their legal systems thus by no means exempts State authorities from their obligation to
abide by the law and the constitution.43 On the other hand, it does not follow that only conventional juridical
power-limitation mechanisms should be allowed. Competition between legal systems may be a complementary
strategy to ensure the people’s freedom as long as the rule of law governs.
5.2 Competition between Legal Orders and the Principle of Equality
Secondly, competition between legal orders challenges traditional concepts of equal protection. The competitive
situation might prompt the legislator, in particular the tax legislator, to violate the principle of equal treatment in
order to preserve or create jobs and sources of tax revenue.44
However, the principle of equality does not demand schematically identical treatment. The common feature of
all domestic and international equal protection regimes is that distinctions which are proportionate to realising
legitimate aims are permissible. The question then is whether, under what conditions and to what extent novel
legislative objectives, such as the need to attract and keep foreign capital in the country, are to be recognised as
legitimate grounds for distinctions made by the law, for example in taxation. Particularly in tax law, one
permissible ground for a differential treatment of taxpayers might be their proneness to migrate. Along these
lines, natural or moral persons likely to leave the country might be permissibly subjected to lower taxation. This
would constitute a departure from the traditional scheme within a “closed state”, namely that taxpayers who are
equally wealthy must be subject to equal taxes.45 Under German constitutional law, to give one example, the
normative justification for such distinctions is the constitutional principle of open statehood.46
5.3 Competition between Legal Orders and Democracy
One main argument of proponents of competition between legal orders is that such competition fosters
democracy. From a public-choice perspective, competition between legal systems rectifies and counteracts the
structural bias of the domestic democratic process. That structural bias arises from the relative lack of
information on the side of the legislator and the disproportionate influence of interest-groups on the legislative
process.47 The structural bias leads to suboptimal laws, i.e. to laws which disproportionately respond to the
interests of influential groups.
But this classic justification of a competition between legal orders – namely that it enhances democracy within
the Nation State – is flawed on several grounds. First, there is the risk that legal competition, rather than
breaking up the political process, may again give preference to special interests. Those players who can “vote
with their feet” more than others are exactly those who are the better lobbyists anyway. The more credible an
actor’s (for example an industry’s) threat of emigration is, the louder is its voice in the political process, too.48
This applies to capital, in particular financial capital, which is much more mobile than labour forces and whose
voice as a result becomes more influential.49 Seen in such terms, competition between legal systems greatly
accentuates the deficiencies of the democratic process rather than compensating for them.
Secondly, competition between legal systems is inseparably linked to political competition, because the
law-maker’s reactions will necessarily take place as part of a political process. The deficits of the political
process thus impinge upon competition between legal systems.50 Therefore, the compensation argument is to
some extent circular.
As a result, legal-systems competition cannot compensate for a lack of democracy in political competition and
therefore does not per se have a democracy-strengthening effect. On the contrary, it even risks to damage the
43
Gerken, L. (1999). Der Wettbewerb der Staaten (p. 56). Tübingen, Germany: Mohr Siebeck.
44
See Swiss Federal Tribunal (Schweizerisches Bundesgericht) BGE 133 I 206, E. 10.2. (2007) on the degressive income tax of the Canton
Obwalden.
45
German Constitutional Court (Bundesverfassungsgericht), BVerfGE 116, 164 (192, paras 98-99 and 111) (2006) –
Standortsicherungsgesetz, Tarifbegrenzung bei gewerblichen Einkünften; see also BVerfGE 110, 274 (299, paras 74 et seq.) (2004) –
Ökosteuer.
46
Di Fabio, U. (2007). Steuern und Gerechtigkeit, JZ, 62, 749-755 (755).
47
Olson, M. (2003). (Ed.). The Logic of Collective Action: Public Goods and the Theory of Groups (21st. ed.). Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press.
48
German Monopolies Commission (Monopolkommission) (2000). Special Report 27 on Systems Competition (Sondergutachten 27
Systemwettbewerb), 17.
49
Sinn. Competition (note 6), p. 60: “Capital, except possibly for corporate capital trapped by divided taxes, will be the big winner of
systems competition.”
50
Monopolkommission (note 48), 19.
53
www.ccsenet.org/ilr
International Law Research
Vol. 3, No. 1; 2014
principle of democracy because the “customers” of the law do not enjoy formally equal standing in the process
of competition (as opposed to the formal equality in the political process guaranteed by the principle of “one
man - one vote”). The “consumers’” de-facto-inequality of influence poses a democratic problem because the
individual choices of law made by some players almost always have an impact on outsiders who will be
subjected to the laws which result from the “competition”. 51 Overall, the unequal positions of the
law-consumers is acceptable in a democratic State only as long as democratic and strictly formally egalitarian
procedures still formally govern the law-making process. Competition between legal systems that is governed by
the principle of unequal market power is not an alternative process to democratic, general and equal elections
and ballots.
Far from viewing competition as an asset to democracy, some critics of the competition paradigm even argue
that competition between legal systems damages democracy because it undermines the power of parliament.
However, the root cause is not the competition in itself but rather the conditions of globalisation which have
opened the possibilities for the “clients” to evade national laws. It is the numerous direct and indirect
choice-of-law-options available to natural and moral persons that cause a loss of control of the State (and of its
parliament). Global interdependence and the mobility of products and capital have reduced manoeuvring space
for Nation States. These phenomena have in themselves weakened democratic self-determination on a national
level. This fact is independent of whether the said phenomena are conceptualised as systems-competition or not.
The democratic law-maker remains free to set its political priorities. Nothing compels national parliaments to
strive to attain a top rank in the legal systems competition. However, any parliament that refuses to participate in
the systems-competition simply exacerbates the problem. Standing on the side line would weaken the Nation
State’s democracy more in its output dimension than entering the competition would. A strengthening of
democratic policy-making can be achieved mainly by accepting competition as a political challenge and by
embedding it legally.
5.4 Competition between Legal Orders and the Social Principle
Competition between legal orders may indirectly generate wealth, in that the “products” in this competition – the
legal rules – develop into better and more demand-oriented conditions for economic and thus wealth-promoting
activities. On the other hand, competition stands in an obvious tension with the principles of the social state and
of solidarity.52
5.4.1 Neglect of Powerless Actors and Lack of Distributive Justice
In a market, the preferences of the more powerful groups (those who can pay a higher price) are better served
than those of the weaker groups. Entities or actors who do not have any voice to express their preferences and to
pay, such as the environment, animals or future generations, are not taken into consideration at all in a pure
market mechanism.
In addition, competition does not allow for any, or only a small degree of, social redistribution. This is
particularly obvious in tax competition. In order to remove the incentive for wealthy taxpayers to migrate to
low-tax jurisdictions, States are inclined to cut taxes, as a result of which the finances available for redistribution
shrink. The policy-shift from direct to indirect taxation – which has taken place in response to the risk of
emigration – also reduces options for redistribution.53
This issue can be framed in terms of justice. The “invisible hand” may guide individuals to unintentionally
promote the public interest by pursuing their own self-interest.54 But this market mechanism creates only
51
See along this line Bachmann, G. (2012). Vertikaler Regulierungswettbewerb im Euopäischen Gesellschaftsrecht. In B. Erle et al. (Eds.),
Festschrift für Peter Hommelhoff zum 70. Geburtstag (pp. 21-44). Köln, Germany: Verlag Dr. Otto Schmidt.
52
See for the social principle on the international plane the International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights; on the national
plane Art. 20 sec. 1 German Constitution (Basic Law, Grundgesetz (GG)); Art. 41 Swiss Federal Constitution, Bundesverfassung (BV). See
for the EU Art. 3 sec. 3 TEU (Lisbon) and Art. 151 et seq. TFEU.
53
See also text with note 60.
54
“[E]very individual … generally, indeed, neither intends to promote the public interest, nor knows how much he is promoting it. … [H]e
intends only his own gain, and he is in this, … led by an invisible hand to promote an end which was no part of his intention. Nor is it always
the worse for the society that it was not part of his intention. By pursuing his own interest he frequently promotes that of the society more
effectually than when he really intends to promote it.” Smith, A. (orig. London 1776). An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of
Nations (Book IV, chap. ii, para. 9, p. 456). Ed. (1979) by Campbell, R. H. et al. Oxford, England: Oxford University Press. “It is not from
the benevolence of the butcher, the brewer, or the baker, that we expect our dinner, but from their regard to their own interest. We address
ourselves, not to their humanity but to their self-love, and never talk to them of our own necessities but of their advantages.” (ibid., Book I,
54
www.ccsenet.org/ilr
International Law Research
Vol. 3, No. 1; 2014
compensatory justice through giving and taking – that is, justitia compensative, but not distributive justice
(justitia distributive).55 This runs counter to the solidarity principle, which must be respected in a social welfare
state.
5.4.2 A Downward Spiral?
The most serious threat to the social principle appears to lie in the much feared downward spiral. A gradual
downward spiral caused by competition could affect, for example, environmental standards, social standards, and
creditor protection in corporate law. A downward spiral in respect of taxes would in the long term erode the tax
base and impoverish the State. The State would be driven, on the one hand, into debt, which would place an
unfair burden on future generations, and on the other, compelled to underperform and reduce governmental tasks,
including in the area of services of general interest. The long-term threat, according to the view of the
competition critics, is self-destruction of the tax-financed State.56
However, the notorious race to the bottom57 is not generally recognised among economists, neither as a
theoretical model nor as an empirical reality.58 Notably Richard Revesz has shown that race-to-the-bottom
arguments are not covered by existing models of interjurisdictional competition. Even if there were a race to the
bottom over environmental standards, regulation on a higher legal level (e.g. by federal law in a federal State or
on the level of international law) would not be an adequate response. States concerned with attracting industry
would reduce the standards in other areas.59
Moreover, the “race-to-the-bottom” hypothesis does not fit with regard to some fields of law, for instance
competition law. In competition law, there is no clear-cut “minimum” and “maximum” level of protection, since
its determination depends on the specific objective of the law which in turn is influenced by the underlying
concept of competition and the model of competitive market economy. The objectives of contemporary national
competition regimes are merely partly of an economic nature. Legal fields, such as competition law do not set
any linear standards, and it is therefore not clear what the “bottom” is.
In other areas of law, in which a “bottom line” can be defined, the expected race to the bottom has in fact not
always occurred. For example, in labour legislation, the transfer of production sites to low-wage-countries has
not led to a lowering of health and safety standards in the industrialised countries. Those standards remain high
thanks to technical progress. In contrast, some erosions are discernible in industrialised countries in relation to
wages and protection against unfair dismissal. But these erosions are due to multiple factors and cannot
necessarily be attributed to the competition with developing States.
Looking at the tax law of some States, no trend to reduce taxes is visible, neither have the tax revenues generally
decreased. However, many countries shift away from direct taxation to indirect taxation, and from the taxation of
mobile capital to the taxation of the more immobile production factor of labour and real estate.60 This can be
interpreted as a reaction to the pressure of capital outflow.
A recent survey of global regulatory competition shows that the competition leads to three types of results.61 In
some areas, regulation has actually ended up at a low level. The main example is the working and safety
regulations on board ships. However, the phenomenon of flags of convenience (registering ships under the laws
of a State with particularly low safety, labour, and environmental standards) hardly allows conclusions to be
drawn about other areas of law. The shipping does not possess any fixed production site nor a territorial location
for services, and also the crew members are universally mobile. Regulatory competition here builds on unique
Chap. ii 2 (26-27)).
55
Pope Benedict XVI. (2009, June 29). Encyclical Caritas in Veritate, para. 35.
56
Kirchhof. Freiheitlicher Wettbewerb (note 5), 44.
57
The term “race to laxity” was coined in 1933 by U.S. Supreme Court Justice Louis Brandeis with regard to the competition among U.S.
Federal States in the area of company law: “Companies were early formed to provide the charters for corporations in states where the cost
was lowest and the laws least restrictive. The states joined in advertising their wares. The race was not one of diligence, but of laxity.” U.S.
Supreme Court, Ligget Co. V. Lee (288 U.S. 517, 558-559 (1933), footnotes omitted).
58
According to the German Monopolies Commission (Monopolkommission) (note 48), 23, the extent of the downward spiral is
overestimated in the public debate.
59
Revesz, R. (1992). Rehabilitating Interstate Competition: Rethinking the Race-to-the-Bottom Rationale for Federal Environmental
Regulation. NYU Law Review, 67, 1210-1254.
60
On the non-existence of a downward spiral and on the shift of the burden of taxation Curzon-Price, V. (2008). Fiscal Competition and the
Optimization of Tax Revenues for Higher Growth (pp. 155-182). In Bergh & Höijer (note 12).
61
Murphy, D. D. (2004). The Structure of Regulatory Competition. Oxford, NY: Oxford University Press, USA.
55
www.ccsenet.org/ilr
International Law Research
Vol. 3, No. 1; 2014
features of the industry. Besides, flags of convenience are less a problem with regard to the contents and the
level of protection and safety standards but rather with regard to the enforcement of those standards. A different
question in this area of law concerns low taxes and low wages. Here, a downward spiral can be observed,
particularly since long-established seafaring nations attempt to stimulate the re-flagging of ships by granting tax
reliefs especially to ship owners.62
Another direction that legal competition can take is to produce agreement on a higher common denominator, the
so-called “race to the top”. This happened at the international level with, for example, the Montreal Protocol on
protection of the ozone layer.63 An example of a “race to the top” at the domestic level is the “California effect”,
i.e. the introduction of higher exhaust emission standards in all U.S. Federal States and at the federal level
according to the Californian model.
The third and by far the most frequent type of regulatory competition is the persistence of heterogeneity of the
standards, despite competition. This is the case in broad areas of regulation, from the law on unfair advertising to
animal welfare. This also applies regionally, as the example of Switzerland shows. Ever since the Swiss Federal
State was founded in 1848, there has been competitive federalism with regard to many regulated professions.
This competition has been enabled by free movement of professionals and the mutual recognition of Cantonal
standards. Still, there is no “race to the bottom” here.64 The density and nature of the Cantonal regulations on
diplomas, licences and permits to practise a profession obviously depend heavily on other factors, such as the
influence of local interest groups and above all on regional cultural values.65 For example, professions in
Protestant Appenzell Ausserrhoden are much less regulated than in Catholic Appenzell Innerrhoden, although
labour and capital indeed moves between the two directly neighbouring Cantons. This means that regulatory
competition exists – but has not led to uniform, let alone specifically low standards.66
In conclusion, no downward spiral per se can be generally attributed to competition between legal systems, and
thus social (and environmental) principles are not jeopardised per se either.
5.5 Competition between Legal Orders and the Public Interest
The central objection raised to allowing competition between legal orders is the danger of neglecting the public
(general) interest.67 This is because when designing his product, a supplier who is in competition focuses on the
customers’ needs and tries to satisfy specific customer groups.
But is a demand-oriented system really opposed to one that is geared to the public interest? There would not be
any contradiction if the public interest were to result from the sum of individual preferences expressed, as it is
assumed by utilitarianism. As Jeremy Bentham famously put it: “The interest of the community then is, what? –
the sum of the interests of the several members who compose it”.68 However, it has been demonstrated that it is
impossible to reproduce faithfully the distribution of individual preferences of the members of a collective (e.g.
of one nation) in democratic decision-making processes and reach one single decision at the same time.
According to the Arrow theorem, it is logically impossible to design collective decision-making procedures
which at least roughly meet minimum requirements for democratic procedures and which at the same time are
consistent. In this sense, there is no “welfare function”.69 This means that, for logical reasons alone, the pursuit
of public-interest objectives cannot be confined to satisfying expressed individual preferences (signalled by
“willingness to pay”) of the “law consumer”. (Nonetheless, decisions in the public interest may, without having
recourse to an asserted “interest” of a non-existent, supra-individual entity, such as the “general public” or
“society”, strive for the fulfilment of assumed and widely shared interests and needs.70)
62
See on these issues König, D. (2009). Flags of Convenience. In R. Wolfrum (Ed.), Max Planck Encyclopedia of Public International Law.
Oxford: Oxford University Press. Retrieved November 14, 2013, from http://www.mpepil.com.
63
Montreal Protocol on Substances That Deplete the Ozone Layer (1987, September 16), revised version in United Nations Treaty Series
(UNTS) (Vol. 1522), p. 3.
64
De Chambrier, A. (2003). Die Verwirklichung des Binnenmarktes bei reglementierten Berufen, Grundlagenbericht zur Revision des BGBM
(Bundesgesetz über den Binnenmarkt). Bern, Switzerland: Seco – Staatssekretariat für Wirtschaft.
65
Feld, L. Regulatory Competition and Federalism in Switzerland (note 30), 24.
66
Ibid., 23.
67
See Kirchhof, P. (Ed.) (2005). Gemeinwohl und Wettbewerb. Heidelberg, Germany: C.F. Müller.
68
Bentham, J. (orig. 1789). An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation (Chap. I, Sec. IV, p. 3). Ed. (1948) by Lafleur, L. J.
New York, NY: Hafner Publishing Company.
69
Arrow, K. J. (1963, orig. 1951). Social Choice and Individual Value (2nd ed.) New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press.
70
Cf. Weale, A. (1998). Public Interest. In E. Craig (Ed.). Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Vol. 7, pp. 832 et seq. (p. 834)). London,
56
www.ccsenet.org/ilr
International Law Research
Vol. 3, No. 1; 2014
Generally speaking, public-interest considerations must combine concerns of effectiveness and of equity. On the
one hand, they take as their starting point actual particular preferences of individuals; on the other hand, the real
or presumed interests of the group are sometimes allowed to prevail.71 It is precisely this tension between the
individual preferences and the collective interest that characterises the concept of public interest. That is why the
procedures for resolving this tension in the concrete case are key. Generally accepted formal principles which
safeguard the “production” of fair public interest decisions are the rules of neutrality, unselfishness,
administrative restraint and responsibility, the ex-ante-circumscription of competences and procedures,
modalities of control, and transparency.
Pure competition is not a suitable method for resolving this tension. This is because competition merely creates
an advantageous legal order for those individuals who hold a powerful market position in the light of whatever
aims and interests they actually pursue. Therefore, competition between legal orders must be supplemented by
other control mechanisms and, where appropriate, be corrected to create a legal system in the public interest.
6. Embedding Legal Systems Competition in a Meta Order
The normative assessment of competition between legal orders in the light of constitutional principles offers a
guideline for the legislative response to that competition, i.e. guidance for how to appropriately frame that
competition legally.
6.1 Are There General Legal Principles which Call for Entering into Regulatory Competition?
Competition is not an end in itself. Nor can any legal obligation which allows or promotes competition between
legal orders be derived from general legal principles. Neither State sovereignty, nor federal guarantees of the
existence of federal States,72 nor the subsidiarity principle73, nor the European fundamental freedoms74 together
with the country-of-origin-principle can be interpreted as requiring competition as a matter of legal principle.
The same is true for the legal concept of private autonomy. From a continental European perspective, private
autonomy justifies the principle of freedom of choice in private international law and thus is a functional
condition of legislatory competition.75 However, this justification holds only as far as third-party interests are
not affected. When it comes to law-making, third parties will inevitably be affected. Therefore, the concept of
private autonomy does not in itself justify or require any State to provide for choice-of-law-rules which in turn
are conducive of a specific type of legal competition.
All mentioned principles (pertaining to international, European, and the domestic law of many States) are merely
conditions for the possibility of legal competition, but not its normative basis. Hence, the idea of embedding the
fact of regulatory competition into legal standards does not flow from any legally binding obligation to ensure
such competition.
Only if the competition of legal orders actually safeguards freedom, compensates for shortcomings in the
democratic process and generates wealth, the “principle” of competition might be considered as a kind of
secondary or auxiliary legitimising principle which may guide legal policy. Obviously, the competition of legal
orders cannot justify the adoption of legal rules and instruments which would otherwise be unconstitutional.
Thus, the answer to the second question asked in the introduction, that is, whether the promotion of the
competition between legal orders may serve as a normative guideline for the national and supranational legislator
and for other State activity is in principle: yes it may, but it need not. The law allows the promotion of
competition between legal orders, but does not prescribe it.
England: Routledge.
71
Koller, P. (2002). Das Konzept des Gemeinwohls. Versuch einer Begriffsexplikation. In W. Brugger et al. (Eds.), Gemeinwohl in
Deutschland, Europa und der Welt (pp. 41-70, (pp. 50-52)). Baden-Baden, Germany: Nomos.
72
See Art. 79 sec. 3 and Art. 29 sec. 3, sentence 4 of the German Basic Law (Grundgesetz, GG); Art. 53 Swiss Federal Constitution; Art. 4
sec. 3 of the U.S. Constitution.
73
See however for the principle of subsidiarity as the “quest for a maximum of competition between the legal orders” Kerber, W. (1998).
Zum Problem einer Wettbewerbsordnung für den Systemwettbewerb. Jahrbuch für neue politische Ökonomie, 17, 199 et seq. (207) (author’s
translation).
74
See on this Terhechte, J. P. (2009). Wettbewerb der Regulierungen als Integrationsstrategie der Europäischen Union? In H.-J. Blanke et al.
(Eds.), Dimensionen des Wettbewerbs – Europäische Integration zwischen Eigendynamik und politischer Gestaltung (pp. 74-98). Tübingen,
Germany: Mohr Siebeck.
75
See below note 82.
57
www.ccsenet.org/ilr
International Law Research
Vol. 3, No. 1; 2014
De lege ferenda, the (meta) legal order should be designed in such a way that the competition of legal orders
develops, but is also controlled, guided and under certain circumstances curtailed, in order to strengthen its
positive impact on the implementation of constitutional principles and to contain the negative effect on them.
The aim is thus the creation of an “order for competition [Wettbewerbsordnung]” as defined by ordo-liberalist
Walter Eucken.76
Such a legal meta order requires two sets of meta rules: first of all, those that make competition between legal
systems possible, ensure its existence and, if necessary, enhance that competition. This set of rules can be
described as law constitutive of competition. The second set consists of rules that counteract as far as possible
the harmful repercussions of competition between legal systems. The regulatory objective of these competition
rules must be to prevent as far as possible “unfair” competition between legal orders. “Unfairness” is measured
by means of constitutional principles which are generally acknowledged in the national and supranational realm.
6.2 The Meta Order Constituting Competition
The body of law establishing competition must first of all contain rules for the so-called parallel process in
competition, that is, for the relationship between the different law-providers. Those rules are, for instance, those
which guarantee that a multiplicity of law-makers persists, because there can of course be no competition when
only one single supplier exists as a monopolist. The principle of sovereignty and federal principles do indeed
guarantee that a multiplicity of potentially law-“offering” actors co-exist.77 Also, legal rules on the allocation of
law-making competencies regulate the relationship of different law-providers amongst themselves. These rules
thus also relate to the parallel process of competition.
Secondly, the direct and indirect choice-of-law-modalities already addressed in the analytical part of this paper
(section 4) must be guaranteed in the exchange relationship in order for competition to flourish. We have seen
that these modalities are mainly democratic elections, freedom of migration, freedom of choice of law in private
international law and free movement of goods.
Free movement of workers is not guaranteed in international law. And in spite of the WTO, trade in goods and
services has only been partially deregulated. Essentially, GATT and GATS have merely removed non-tariff
barriers to mobility. Other barriers – such as tariffs – are being gradually reduced qua negotiation processes.
Moreover, measures that hamper the free movement of goods and services, but which are justified to protect
national public interests, remain permissible (Art. XX GATT, Art. XIV GATS). Capital movements have even
less been deregulated: the international flow of capital, except for payment transactions, is not free. Sovereign
States may restrict these flows (cf. Art. IV (1) and (3) IMF-Agreement). Under Art. XXX (d) IMF-Agreement,
only payment transactions (but not other forms of capital flows) are privileged. The WTO does not foresee the
general liberalisation of capital flows either but again only of payment transactions (Art. XI GATS).78 To
conclude, some of the core legal conditions which would be necessary to establish a genuine competition of legal
systems are lacking at the international level.
Within the EU and associated States such as Switzerland,79 “entry/exit rules” have only been guaranteed by the
basic Union freedoms (free movement of workers, free establishment, free movement of goods, services) since
that moment when those freedoms have been construed in the case law and in legal practice as so-called
prohibitions on Member State restrictions of these freedoms. In the early days of the EU, those basic freedoms
had been more narrowly understood to guarantee only non-discrimination (in relation to the regulating Member
State’s own nationals). In that phase, the basic EU freedoms did not yet automatically guarantee mobility,
because the standards of the country of origin and the country of destination had to be complied with
cumulatively (e.g. by the businessman who sought to establish a residence in another Member State). Even today,
those Member States’ restrictions on basic freedoms which are allowed in order to protect overriding (domestic)
public interests under EU-law continue to constitute barriers to mobility. And these barriers in turn hinder
76
Eucken, W. (1990/1952). Grundsätze der Wirtschaftspolitik (6th ed.). Tübingen, Germany: Mohr Siebeck, 245-250.
77
See above note 72.
78
See Ruffert, M. (2009). Free Flow of Capital. In R. Wolfrum (Ed.), Max Planck Encyclopedia of Public International Law. Oxford,
England: Oxford University Press 2009, Retrieved November 14, 2013, from http://www.mpepil.com.
79
The free movement of persons is guaranteed by the agreement between the European Community and its Member States, and the Swiss
Confederation, on the free movement of persons of 21 June 1999 (SR 0.142.112.681). See for the “autonomous adoption” (i.e. copying) of
the EU’s country-of-origin-rule for technical norms and standards by Switzerland, including the “Cassis de Dijon” exception for the
protection of overriding public-interest-objectives (see note 80) the Swiss Federal Act on Technical Barriers to Trade (Bundesgesetz über die
technischen Handelshemmnisse, THG) of 25 June 2009, Bundesblatt 2009, 4463 (insertion of sec. 16a THG in 2009).
58
www.ccsenet.org/ilr
International Law Research
Vol. 3, No. 1; 2014
competition between legal orders.80 Furthermore, harmonisation of the domestic law of the Member States, as
far as it goes, excludes competition between legal orders. This means that competition between Member States’
laws in the EU is only a residuum of the regulatory leeway the Member States are left with once they have
complied with the prohibitions on restrictions of basic freedoms on the one hand, and with the obligation to
harmonise their law on the other hand.81
As a result, a trade-off exists with regard to the conditions of legal diversity and factor mobility. Diversity of
legal orders is the prerequisite for competition between those systems. On the other hand, this legal diversity
itself is a barrier to mobility, while mobility in turn is likewise a prerequisite for legal competition. It is
impossible to optimise both functional conditions at the same time – full diversity of law and unhampered
mobility. The improvement of one condition inevitably deteriorates the other.
6.3 (Re-)Restriction of the Selection Modalities?
The second set of rules for regulating or taming legal competition consists of legal barriers to unfair, excessive
and otherwise harmful competition between legal orders. I will focus on two main strategies: first, (re-)restriction
of the selection modalities, and second, rules of fair competition.
Some of the modalities of direct and indirect choice of law can be considered as an outgrowth of legal or even
constitutional guarantees of freedom. For example, freedom of choice under conflict-of-law-provisions –
particularly in contract law – is in continental Europe regarded as an expression of private autonomy and of the
constitutional liberty of citizens. 82 Some consider freedom of choice as being required by customary
international law and even as a necessary consequence of the basic freedoms of the single European market.
Indeed, allowing a company to choose one legal order for all its subsidies facilitates the firm’s mobility and
therefore seems to honour the EU-guarantee of freedom of establishment. On the other hand, the
choice-of-law-option can be compared to a “selling modality” in this sense of the ECJ’s Keck-decision,83 which
would mean that the choice of law does not even come within the scope of the EU fundamental freedom in the
first place. Hence, a Member State’s restriction of the freedom to choose the law does not always imply a
potential curtailment of EU basic freedoms.
This issue is viewed differently in the Common law tradition. In the Common law, party autonomy with regard
to the choice of the applicable substantive law and with regard to the choice of the forum has only been accepted
alongside with the European harmonisation of private international law (choice-of-law-rules).84 The same view
has been espoused by the French doctrine of objective connection regarding contractual obligations.85 Seen from
the viewpoint of both the latter, the options for choice under conflict-of-law-provisions could in theory be
restricted again without violating the basic private law principle of party autonomy. Such a restriction does
however not seem likely in real life, it would run counter current legal trends.
We have seen that the second choice-of-law-modality was the “exit”-type modality. Here we must distinguish
the two variants mentioned above (section 4.2.2.), and their use by natural persons and corporate entities. The
first variant, change of nationality by natural persons – that is, the exit by citizens from their State – may not be
categorically prohibited in an open society. For example, Art. 15 sec. 2 of the Universal Declaration of Human
Rights of 10 December 1948 stipulates: “No one shall be arbitrarily deprived of his nationality nor denied the
right to change his nationality”.86 However, “openness” of a society by no means requires that natural persons
must be allowed to change their nationality at will any time. Restrictions on the choice of nationality, imposed
by both the releasing State and the naturalising State, in particular through the requirement of a minimum period
of residence and a domicile in the new State, are permissible.
80
See as an example for limitations of the free movement of goods Art. 36 TFEU (ex-Art. 30 EC Treaty) and ECJ, case 120/78, Rewe v.
Bundesmonopolverwaltung für Branntwein (“Cassis de Dijon”), ECR 1979, 649.
81
Teichmann, C. (2006). Binnenmarktkonformes Gesellschaftsrecht. Berlin, Germany: de Gruyter Recht, 383.
82
Institut de droit international (1991, August 31). Resolution “L’autonomie de la volonté des parties dans les contrats internationaux entre
personnes privés” Retrieved November 14, 2013, from www.idi-iil.org.
83
ECJ, joined cases C-267/91 and C-268/91, Criminal proceedings against Bernard Keck and Daniel Mithouard, ECR 1993 I-06097.
84
Mills, A (2009). The Confluence of Public and Private International Law (pp. 292-93). Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press.
85
See seminally Battifol, H (1960). Subjectivisme et objectivisme dans le droit international privé des contrats, In Faculté de droit et des
sciences économiques de Toulouse (Ed.), Mélanges offerts à Jacques Maury (Vol. 1, pp. 39-58), Paris, France: Librairie Dalloz et Sirey.
86
To the same effect Art. 8 of the European Convention on Nationality of 6 November 1997, ETS no. 166.
59
www.ccsenet.org/ilr
International Law Research
Vol. 3, No. 1; 2014
The choice of the law applicable to moral persons, especially corporations, may be regulated as well. So the
conversion of a company incorporated under the law of one EU-Member State into a company governed by the
law of a second Member State may be regulated by that second Member State.87
“Exit” through emigration (without a change of nationality) is likewise guaranteed as a basic or human right.88
Within the EU, emigration is additionally guaranteed as a basic European freedom (freedom of movement of
workers and freedom of establishment). Bans on leaving a country for natural persons along the lines of the
former German Democratic Republic annihilate this right and constitute blatant human rights violations.
A different question is the admissibility of indirect restrictions of the basic rights or basic freedoms, as it is found,
for example, in the levying of a departure tax. Examples are the Russian “diploma tax”, the “Bhagwati” tax for
the compensation of the “brain drain” from developing countries as well as the “exit taxes” in some States.89
Here one would have to discuss, first, whether such a tax may be established in conformity with the concept of
taxation. Justifying the imposition of a tax on a particular person by pointing to the taxed person’s prior
utilisation of the State’s infrastructure or to him or her having received social welfare benefits preceding the
emigration does not appear to be in conformity with the idea of taxation. It is not in conformity because it would
thwart the basic idea that tax obligations are independent from specific benefits received by the State. Another
possible justification of exit taxes, namely levying them solely on the basis of a person’s nationality, appears to
be problematic from the public international law perspective. In any case, such a tax would have to be applied
without discrimination which means that it could not be imposed on emigrants only.90
From the viewpoint of constitutional, international, and EU-law, the question is under which conditions and in
which constellations the restriction of basic rights or basic freedoms effected by such a departure tax would
exceptionally be justifiable as a defensive measure in the competition between legal orders, in particular with
regard to moral persons in order to protect overriding public interests. According to the European Court of
Justice (ECJ), French taxes which were charged on increases in value of company securities when a taxpayer
transferred his tax residence outside France unduly restricted the freedom of establishment. The objective of
preventing tax evasion could be achieved by measures that are less coercive or less restrictive of the freedom of
establishment, for example, by providing for the taxation of taxpayers returning to their home country after
realising their increases in value during a relatively brief stay in another Member State. Such a taxation would
apparently be compatible with the freedom of establishment. The structural difference between the basic
freedoms under EU-law and the fundamental right to emigrate does not seem to play a role in this context.91
One could argue further that the selective “exit” of more or less virtual parts of large companies to save on taxes
does not even come within the scope of the right to leave the country or the right to business or freedom of
contract or establishment. This would mean that an EU Member State’s attempt to prevent such “exit” would not
constitute a violation of the EU fundamental freedoms. Or, such a business design could possibly be qualified as
an abuse of those basic rights or freedoms. Then, the company would be precluded from relying on the EU
freedom establishment, and Member States could lawfully restrict or prevent their “exit”, too. (This argument
has however not been accepted by the ECJ, which in Cadbury Schweppes held that the establishment of a
company in a Member State for the purpose of benefiting from more favourable (tax) legislation does not in
itself suffice to constitute an abuse of the freedom of establishment.92)
These possible legal strategies to prevent business exits are, however, difficult to implement from a legal and
factual point of view, regardless of their economic rationality (or lack of rationality). The policy focus should be
placed on reducing the incentive to vote against a legal system. This means, in principle, facing up to
competition between legal systems.
87
Cf. obiter dictum in ECJ, case C-210/06, Cartesio (note 34), paras 111-112.
88
Art. 13 sec. 2 Universal Declaration of Human Rights; Art. 12 ICCPR; Art. 2 sec. 2 of Prot. No. 4 to the ECHR.
89
See Schön, W. Steuerstaat und Freizügigkeit. In Becker & Schön (note 13), 41 et seq. (46-50) with further references.
90
See ibid. 60-74.
91
ECJ, case C-9/02, Hughes de Lasteyrie de Sailant, ECR 2004, I-2409, paras 38-54.
92
ECJ, case C-196/04, Cadbury Schweppes v. Commissioners of Ireland Revenue, judgment of 12 September 2006 (Grand Chamber), paras
35-38. According to ECJ, Centros (note 34), para. 27, “the fact that a national of a Member State who wishes to set up a company chooses to
form it in the Member State whose rules of company law seem to him the least restrictive … cannot, in itself, constitute an abuse of the right
of establishment.”
60
www.ccsenet.org/ilr
International Law Research
Vol. 3, No. 1; 2014
6.4 Identification of Unfair Regulatory Practices
In practice, the most important strategy for guiding competition between legal orders are the rules on fair
competition. We must first form an idea which competitive actions taken by law-providers can reasonably be
deemed “unfair”. In order to determine this, one has to gain a clear idea of the goods to be protected. From a
constitutional perspective, the goods to be protected are the above-mentioned constitutional principles.
6.4.1 “Harmful” Tax Competition
Unfair regulatory practices have been discussed up to now mainly in relation to competition between tax
regulations. 93 At the end of the 1990s, packages of measures were devised in the context of the OECD94 and
the EU95 against so-called harmful tax competition. The idea of “harmful tax regimes” is difficult to grasp in
legal terms. The OECD-report defines harmful preferential tax regimes by four key factors:96 first, when a State
imposes no or very low tax rates; second, the “ring fencing” of regimes; third, the lack of transparency in the
operation of a regime; and fourth, the lack of effective exchange of information.97 According to the OECD, a
State may be qualified as a tax haven also when it does not require actors which seek to come under its (tax)
jurisdiction to perform any substantial economic activity within the State itself.98 Finally, the OECD gives the
following auxiliary criteria for the determination whether a legal tax regime is “harmful”: when the tax base is
defined artificially; when the regime fails to adhere to international transfer pricing principles; when it exempts
foreign source income from the residence country tax; when the tax rate or tax base is negotiable; where there
exist bank secrecy provisions; when the country offers access to a wide network of tax treaties (which may
enhance the benefits of harmful preferential tax regimes); or when the regime is promoted as a tax minimisation
vehicle.99 The EU-code of conduct for business taxation of 1997 qualifies, in a slightly different terminology,
the same measures as “harmful” as the OECD.100
Taxation policies reflect different, culturally conditioned views. Against this background it is difficult to define
the point at which the legitimate exercise of taxation sovereignty turns into unfair “poaching” on foreign tax
territory. The limit must be determined by means of various factors, and here the criteria formulated by the
OECD and the EU are only a first approach. Furthermore, we must note that there are different degrees of
harmfulness. Finally, there may be reasons for justifying certain tax measures, in particular a State’s need to
compensate for natural locational disadvantages.101 For example, Art. 107 sec. 3 lit. a) TFEU declares as
compatible with the common market aids to promote the economic development of areas where the standard of
living is abnormally low or where there is serious underemployment, and with a view to the structural, economic
and social situation of certain regions.
6.4.2 Unfair “Regulatory” Subsidies?
Generally speaking, legal practice and courts should first of all seek to draw up unambiguous criteria for
defining unfair or harmful regulatory practices. Otherwise a meta order for legal competition would not be
operational. In order to determine whether a legal regime is “unfair”, one might have recourse to the
characteristics established within the EU for unallowable and allowable subsidies and those subject to
93
See in State practice on combating “unfair” tax competition the respective provisions in double taxation agreements, e.g. Art. 28 sec. 2 of
the double taxation agreement Germany − Austria of 24 August 2000: “Der Ansässigkeitsstaat ist berechtigt, seine innerstaatlichen
Rechtsvorschriften zur Abwehr von Steuerumgehungen anzuwenden, um missbräuchlichen Gestaltungen oder unfairem Steuerwettbewerb zu
begegnen.” (“The country of residence is entitled to apply its domestic provisions against tax avoidance in order to deal with abusive legal
constructs or unfair tax competition”, translation by the author).
94
See OECD (1998). Harmful Tax Competition: An Emerging Global Issue. Paris, France: OECD. The OECD differentiates between “tax
havens” and (merely) “harmful preferential tax regimes”. Subsequently, as part of the “OECD Project on Harmful Tax Practices”, progress
reports were published on a regular basis (of 2000, 2001, 2004 and 2006). See also “Overview of the OECD’s Work on Countering
International Tax Evasion” of 16 September 2009.
95
Conclusions of the Ecofin Council Meeting on 1 December 1997 concerning taxation policy (OJ EC 1998/C 2/01 et seq.); Annex 1:
Resolution of the Council and the Representatives of the Governments of the Member States, Meeting Within the Council of 1 December
1997 on a code of conduct for business taxation (OJ EC 1998, C 2/02 et seq.).
96
OECD 1998 (note 94), paras 57-84; summary in ibid., 27, box II.
97
See on the last criterion the critical statements of Switzerland and Luxembourg in the annex of the OECD-report 1998, 76 et seq.
98
Summary in OECD 1998, 23, box I.
99
Ibid., paras 68-79.
100
See Art. B of the code of conduct (note 95).
101
Cf. OECD 1998 (note 94), paras 31 and 27.
61
www.ccsenet.org/ilr
International Law Research
Vol. 3, No. 1; 2014
approval.102 Within the EU, the State aid prohibition rule as laid down in Art. 107 TFEU (ex-Art. 87 EC Treaty)
is in fact already applied to those preferential taxes that threaten to distort competition.103
However, determining that a specific regulation is equal to a subsidy (a subsidy in form of laws, without giving
any money) would have to be based upon very complex political considerations. Currently, no consensus exists
about this matter at the international level.104 The intention and purpose of the legal prohibitions on (traditional,
financial) subsidies are such that they seem hardly applicable to competition between legal systems. It is
therefore difficult to tackle regulatory competition within the legal framework of subsidies.
6.4.3 Normative Dumping?
The existing WTO anti-dumping provisions105 against the alleged under-regulation of certain areas of law,
polemically known as “normative dumping” or “ecological and social dumping” cannot be applied here. A
product is, according to the legal definition given in Art. 2 of the Antidumping Agreement,106 “dumped”, when
it is “introduced into the commerce of another country at less than its normal value”, that is when “the export
price of the product exported from one country to another is less than the comparable price, in the ordinary
course of trade, for the like product when destined for consumption in the exporting country”.
Because the discrepancy in wages and social or environmental standards is a normal consequence of the market
mechanism, it is controversial whether the elimination of this competitive advantage of “low-wage-countries” is
desirable or should on the contrary be prohibited on the ground that it is in reality a protectionist strategy of the
industrialised countries. Given this uncertainty, even the concept of normative dumping is not currently one on
which a consensus could be reached. Anti-dumping law is thus not applicable to competition between legal
systems.
6.4.4 Non-Regulation of Inhumane Production Conditions
The counterexample is the State’s toleration of forced labour.107 This is an unfair practice in competition
between legal orders. It is unfair because a locational advantage is based on inhumane production conditions.
Between a competitive advantage that has to be accepted and clearly unfair forced labour there is a broad grey
area of employment relationships and working conditions, the “fairness” of which is questionable. A distinction
should be drawn here between occupational safety and health and accident prevention on the one hand and
wages and protection against unfair dismissal on the other. Overly lax regulation in the former area should be
qualified as an unfair regulatory practice in competition between legal orders for production locations. Because
of varying societal expectations regarding health and security, the threshold beyond which conditions are “unfair”
does not need to be identical everywhere on the world. This graduation is being taken into account by the
International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights. The contracting parties are only required to
“achieve the full realization” of the right to safe and healthy working conditions “progressively”.108 Standards
on work safety and hygiene are clearly unfair when the local legal system would qualify them as violative of
personal rights of workers.
6.5 Elements of the Quality-Ensuring Meta Order
The meta order for curbing the negative repercussions of competition between legal orders would have to
contain a number of general elements.
Rules of international cooperation: the meta order would, firstly, have to establish international cooperation on
combating unfair practices.109 An example from the area of taxation is the OECD’s strategy for improving
transparency and information exchange.110
102
Art. 107 sec. 1 TFEU. See for the WTO Art. XVI GATT and the WTO Agreement on Subsidies and Countervailing Measures (1994, April
15) (OJ 1994 L 336/156).
103
ECJ, case C-172/03, Heiser, ECR 2005, I-1627, esp. para. 27.
104
Trachtman, J. (1993). International Regulatory Competition, Externalization, and Jurisdiction. Harvard International Law Journal, 34, at
47, 50 and 91.
105
Art. VI GATT and the Agreement on Implementation of Article VI of the General Agreement on Tariffs and Trade 1994 (“Antidumping
Agreement”), OJ 1994 L 336/ 103, implemented in the EU by Regulation No. 384/96, OJ EC 1996, L 56/1.
106
Note 105.
107
Prohibited under Art. 4 ECHR; Art. 8 sec. 3 CCPR.
108
See Art. 2 sec. 1 and 2, Art. 7 lit. b) and 12 sec. 2 lit. b) ICSECR.
109
See in favour of a multilateral approach to combating unfair tax competition Avi-Yonah. Welfare State (note 40).
110
See the OECD-Document (2009, September 16). Overview of the OECD’s Work on Countering International Tax Evasion. One of the
62
www.ccsenet.org/ilr
International Law Research
Vol. 3, No. 1; 2014
Rules for selective intensification of legal order competition: the quality-ensuring meta order could also
selectively seek to intensify competition. This could be done, for example, by broadening the direct
choice-of-law-options in private international law. If low standards can be voted out by those people or entities
who are put at a disadvantage by them, a “race to the top” will be set in motion. For example, the EU-Regulation
on the law applicable to non-contractual obligations111 allows the victim a choice of law for environmental
damage caused at multiple locations.112 This grants persons who have suffered damage access to higher
environmental standards and is thus suitable to set in motion a race to the top.
Regulation by civil society: furthermore, the meta order of legal systems competition would have to overcome
the dichotomy of State versus market, for example, by recognising civil society as a third force.113 Civil society
groups exert an influence on the further development of legal systems in a way that is different both from the
sovereignty mode of action and from the competition mode. What is known as “civil regulation” results from an
interaction between private, social and governmental players.114 When acting in the form of civil regulation,
specific legitimacy deficits of the participating groups (for example each group’s bias) might to some extent
cancel each other out (or neutralise each other). Thus, civil regulation could be promoted and designed in a way
so as to contribute to ensuring fair competition between legal systems.
Conflict resolution rules: finally, the meta order would have to provide for conflict resolution mechanisms to
ensure the quality of legal systems competition. One example is the special, consultative, non-adversarial
conflict resolution mechanisms that exist in EU-law – but which have never been used to date – for provisions of
national law of Member States that distort the conditions in the internal market.115
6.6 Selective Harmonisation of Law
It has been asserted that competition of the laws spontaneously and gradually brings about the exactly
preference-matching degree of a “natural” convergence of laws. If that assertion were correct, concerted, formal
agreements or centralised obligations of legal harmonisation would be superfluous, and an over-excessive
levelling down could be avoided, too. In contrast to a deliberate top-down harmonisation, the assumed
“bottom-up” convergence brought about by competition would not be formally fixed, and it would thus remain
flexible and reversible. Under this assumption, the result of the competition of differing legal regimes would
ultimately be its own abrogation. The reason is that the final stage of legal convergence would amount to an
annihilation of the freedom of choice of laws, and the concomitant incentives to improve the laws supplied
would also disappear.
However, competition does not seem to bring about any “natural” convergence of the law. In fact, in legal areas
with a high degree of competition, e.g. in contract or company law, a “natural” convergence is not discernible.116
This is not surprising, because a convergence could only be expected if the majority of law-customers showed
the same preferences on norms. This is only the case for so-called “homogeneous”, i.e. neutral norms.117
indispensable procedural features of this cooperation is meanwhile the supply of information on request (cf. Art. 26 OECD-Model Tax
Convention on Income and on Capital of 17 July 2008 (http://www.oecd.org/dataoecd/43/57/42219418.pdf)). Since the withdrawals of the
“reservations” on Art. 26 Model Convention by Switzerland, Belgium, Luxemburg, and Austria, all OECD Member States accept the
principle of supplying “foreseeably relevant” information “on request”, which can be refused on ordre-public-grounds.
111
Regulation (EC) No 864/2007 of the European Parliament and of the Council of 11 July 2007 on the law applicable to non-contractual
obligations (“Rome II”).
112
Art. 7 of the Regulation (Environmental Damage) runs: “The law applicable to a non-contractual obligation arising out of environmental
damage or damage sustained by persons or property as a result of such damage shall be the law determined pursuant to Article 4(1), unless
the person seeking compensation for damage chooses to base his or her claim on the law of the country in which the event giving rise to the
damage occurred.”
113
See Hannah Arendt’s differentiation between the public, private and social sphere, which anticipated the rise of civil society already 50
years ago (Arendt, H. (1958). The Human Condition (pp. 35-45). Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press).
114
Peters, A., Förster, T., Koechlin, L. (2009). Towards Non-state Actors as Effective, Legitimate, and Accountable Standard Setters. In A.
Peters et al. (Eds.), Non-state Actors as Standard Setters (pp. 492-562). Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press.
115
Art. 116 and 117 TFEU (ex-Articles 96 and 97 EC). Art. 116 TFEU: “Where the Commission finds that a difference between the
provisions laid down by law, regulation or administrative action in Member States is distorting the conditions of competition in the internal
market and that the resultant distortion needs to be eliminated, it shall consult the Member States concerned.” See in favour of applying these
rules for settling disputes over on tax competition Schön. Steuerwettbewerb in Europa (note 40), 358.
116
See for company law in Europe Bratton, W. W., McCahery, J. A., Vermeulen, E. P. M. (2009). How Does Corporate Mobility Affect
Lawmaking? A Comparative Analysis, American Journal of Comparative Law, 57, 347-385.
117
Seminally Ogus, A. (1999). Competition between National Legal Systems: A Contribution of Economic Analysis to Comparative Law,
63
www.ccsenet.org/ilr
International Law Research
Vol. 3, No. 1; 2014
However, this type of norms is scarce, for even seemingly neutral norms, such as rules on formalities and
procedures, tend to favour some interests and particular parts of society while being rather disadvantageous to
others.
In the absence of a “natural” convergence, an essential component of the meta order of legal systems
competition must be selective harmonisation of law. This is not necessarily a hindrance to or suppression of the
competition of rule-makers, but may intensely contribute to creating and embedding such competition.118 The
selective harmonisation should concern, firstly, procedures. First and foremost, the rules on information should
be uniform. Informed decisions are an essential precondition for an unimpaired competition of legal systems
triggered through “exit”, because information which is easily available helps to reduce mobility costs.119
Secondly, in order to prevent legal standards from falling below a tolerable level, the aim should be the
harmonisation of substantive standards at a minimum level, in particular in the areas of occupational safety and
environmental standards.120 For example, in the EU, technical standards are being harmonised under a “new
approach”. Here legislative harmonisation is confined to laying down the essential requirements, conformity
with which will entitle a product to free movement within the Union. The harmonisation is realised by
private-public standards bodies upon consultation of all societal groups likely to be affected (e.g. consumers),
and with the assistance of the EU Commission.121 Beyond such minimal harmonisation, a competition of
standards persists.122 Another example is the international harmonisation of the rules on the determination of the
taxable base – as opposed to the determination of the tax scale (i.e. the rates and the progression) which should
be left to the mechanisms of competition.123
As long as international harmonisation agreements are rescindable, the participating States will be able to
denounce them and thereby retain residual control. Thus, “vertical competition” (between the supra-national
harmonised regime and the national regime) will continue to be operative. The upcoming research task is to
identify variables to achieve the optimal mix between legal competition and cooperation.124
7. Conclusion: Competition and Human Dignity
The answer to the analytical question raised in this paper is that the description of the evolution of legal order in
terms of “competition” does convey some analytical benefit. We can meaningfully say that there is competition
between legal orders. That competition is incomplete, however, particularly because the competitive cycle is
often interrupted by weak selection pressure and due to selection inaccuracy.
My normative analysis of this regulatory competition has used some legal (even constitutional) principles as
benchmarks, namely liberty, equality, democracy, the social principle and the public interest. The assessment of
the suitability of legal systems competition, considered as a possible process for securing freedom, democracy,
and so on, and of the way in which said competition can be framed by a meta order, depends on the conception
that the observer forms of the State and of the democratic process. Anyone who thinks that the State which
furthers the public interest is a myth anyway125 will rate on the high side the freedom- and equality-promoting
and solidarity-facilitating potentials of competition between legal orders, and will view competition as a useful
corrective measure against excessive taxation and regulation. However, the purely sociological finding that the
State and the democratic process are necessarily “captured” by certain interest groups is in conflict with the legal
analysis which postulates that the State and democracy are normative concepts and thus to a certain extent
counterfactual. The argument of “capture” therefore carries only limited weight in the juridical discourse.
Constitutional lawyers recognise the fundamental ambivalence of the State, which on the one hand is able to
contain the war of all against all, but which on the other hand can, as an untamed Leviathan, bring about
intolerable injustice. Given this fundamental ambivalence, competition between States and their legal orders over
ICLQ, 48, 405 et seq.; see also Muir-Watt. Aspects économiques (note 26), 79-82.
118
Teichmann. Gesellschaftsrecht (note 41), at 386.
119
Ibid., 385-86.
120
See for minimal harmonisation in the field of environment Articles 192-193 TFEU (ex-Art. 175-176 EC).
121
Completing the Internal Market: White Paper for the Commission to the European Council (28-29 June 1985), COM (85) 310 final
(1985), paras 67-73.
122
See for a prohibition of harmonisation Art. 153 sec. 2 lit. a) TFEU (ex-Art. 137 sec. 2 EC Treaty).
123
Gerken, Märkt, Schick. Steuerwettbewerb (note 40), at 266.
124
Esty, D., Geradin, D. (2000). Regulatory Co-opetition, Journal of International Economic Law, 3, 235-255; Trachtman, J. (2008). The
Economic Structure of International Law (pp. 62-63). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press,.
125
Cf. Buchanan, J. M. (2003). Public Choice: Politics without Romance, Policy 19/no. 3, 13 et seq.
64
www.ccsenet.org/ilr
International Law Research
Vol. 3, No. 1; 2014
their product “law” should be understood (and built up) as process which is complementary to the traditional
legal devices for guaranteeing the fundamental principles: liberty, equality, democracy, solidarity and orientation
at the common good of a given society. Competition can function in such a complementary way if it is
meaningfully integrated into a competition order.
A fundamental component of this competition order is to safeguard respect of inalienable legal principles.
Inalienability means that the principles are to be respected regardless of anyone’s willingness to “pay” for their
respect, a willingness which would manifest itself primarily in “voice” or non-“exit”. These principles must
remain legally protected as a fixed point, independently of and transcending competition between legal orders.
The reason is that they are things – to quote Kant126 – that do not have a price, but a dignity.
Acknowledgement
I wish to thank the anonymous reviewers for useful comments on the initially submitted version of the
manuscript. The paper develops further ideas first presented in: Peters, A. (2010). Wettbewerb von
Rechtsordnungen. In Veröffentlichungen der Vereinigung der Staatsrechtslehrer 69 (Ed.), Gemeinwohl durch
Wettbewerb? (pp. 7-56). Berlin, Germany: de Gruyter.
Copyrights
Copyright for this article is retained by the author(s), with first publication rights granted to the journal.
This is an open-access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution
license (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/3.0/).
126
“In the realm of ends everything has either a price or an intrinsic value. Anything with a price can be replaced by something else as its
equivalent, whereas anything that is above all price and therefore admits of no equivalent has intrinsic value.” Kant, I. (orig. 1785, 1999).
Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press, at 33. Note that the German original uses the
term: ‘Würde’ (dignity), not “intrinsic value”.
65

Documentos relacionados